http://dx.doi.org/10.24016/2025.v11.448

LETTER TO THE EDITOR

 

 

The term “Mental” within Mental Health is not Dualist

 

Santiago Castiello1, Yancarlo Lizandro Ojeda Aguilar2, Darwin Gutierrez-Guevara3*

1 Wu Tsai Institute, Yale University, United States

2 Universidad Autónoma de Aguascalientes, Mexico

3 Asociación Peruana Contextual Conductual de Psicología, Peru.

 

* Correspondencia: dgutierrezguevara@gmail.com.

 

Received: February 20, 2025 | Reviewed: March 05, 2024 | Accepted: March 09, 2025 | Published Online: April 22, 2025.

 

CITARLO COMO:

Castiello, S., Ojeda Aguilar, Y., Gutierrez-Guevara, D. (2025). The term “Mental” within Mental Health is not Dualist. Interacciones, 11, e448. http://dx.doi.org/10.24016/2025.v11.448

 

 

Dear Editor,

 

In a well written piece published in Interacciones, Carpio et al. (2024) accused the concept of mental health as dualist. Based on a theoretical analysis, our aims are to address: (1) a philosophical issue with the accusations, and (2) comment on the impact in the research community of these accusations. In this letter we present a clearer and more valid view to a longstanding conflict in interbehaviourist psychology: Cartesian Dualism (CD) usually referred to as dualism. Carpio and colleagues (C&all) recapitulate a general critique to CD and used those arguments to flank the notion of Mental Health. In addition, they proposed an interesting approach to analyze affective disorders from an interbehaviourst framework, nevertheless they provide an alternative concept for affective behavioral change.

First, we agree with C&all with respect that the World Health Organization may not provide an exhaustive philosophical definition for the concept of ‘mental’ when defining mental health. Although perhaps their goal is not to provide exhaustive philosophical definitions but provide general definitions for a common understanding of health. Second, we also agree that CD is not the best fit for psychological science nor psychiatry (e.g., Miller et al., 2020). Third, we agree that a common use of the mind as “internal” is incompatible with CD (see more details in Burgos & Killeen, 2019). However, we could not see references pointing to any Mental Health scientist assuming CD and using the term “internal”.

Even if we agree with some arguments from C&all, we disagree with a core aspect in their work, a mistake also found elsewhere (e.g., Uttal, 2004; Kantor, 1978; Baum, 2011). The flaw in their critique of Mental Health starts with the assumption that “mental” implies CD. First, we define CD then we explain C&all’s error theoretical mistake. CD is comprised by two theses (Burgos, 2016): i) the ontological thesis of Substance Dualism (SD) the res cogitans―soul or mind― and res extensa―physical body― are substantially distinct (Rozemond, 1998); and the Causal Interaction Thesis (CIT) mind and body are causally related. CD is the sum of SD and CIT (Descartes, 1641/2013), i.e., the mind and the body are fundamentally different substances (SD), and these substances hold a causal relation (CIT). However, apart from CD and from a logical point of view, these theses are independent, but also mutually exclusive. The dualistic aspect of CD is given by SD and not by CIT. CD was rejected since its early development by Pierre Gassendi (Voss, 1997) and Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia (Shapiro, 2007, see details in Burgos, 2016). The bases of the rejection were: if mind and body are different substances (SD), they cannot interact (~CIT). If they interact (CIT), they cannot be part of the same substance (~SD), therefore one cannot hold both SD and CIT. Generally, CIT is used to describe mentalism, which does not assume SD.

In their critique, C&all understand dualism as mind and body being distinct and causally linked (i.e., CD), for example: “causal relationship is again postulated between events, processes, or mental events […] and the physical alterations” (pp. 3). However, postulating mental causation implies that the mind and body cannot be different substances, i.e., CIT à ~SD (CIT implies the negation of SD). As shown before ―and as argued years ago by Pierre Gassendi and Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia― it is logically invalid to hold both SD and CIT as in the case of CD. Thus, C&all accusations that mind-body causation imply dualism cannot be held. In the same way, given that the concept of mental health implies mental causation (CIT, i.e., mentalism), automatically that mental health implies the absence of dualism. Lastly, if psychiatrists would presume CD (i.e., accepting SD and CIT), it would make no sense at all to prescribe medications, given that drugs only directly affect the body, and would have no chance on changing the mind. Mentalism, as the case of Mental Health via mental causation (CIT), is completely compatible with a monist form such as materialism (Burgos, 2022). Mentalism turns also to be a good solution to integrate neuroscience and psychology, and it turns out to be the philosophical bases for psychologists who win Nobel Prizes, such as Geoffrey Hinton (e.g., Rumelhart, et al., 1986). But this is an issue beyond the scope of this letter.

A second and distinct argument is at the sociological level. C&all accuse researchers and professionals within the field of Mental Health of being dualists, which as we describe above: is wrong. We believe declaring that mentalism and dualism are no scientific enough does not help for the development of psychology in Latin America. Sustaining these types of accusations demeaning Mental Health is to consider that all psychologies should follow only one correct theory over all the others (e.g., interbehaviorism), irrespective of their context and specific goals. Professional practice in Mental Health improves to the extent that it can produce research that improve clinical outcomes in patients, e.g., psychoanalysis for long term depression (Fonagy, et al., 2015).

Accusing the WHO for not having an adequate philosophical definition of Mental Health, regardless of the circumstantial use of the term, is a categorical error (Ryle, 2009; López Valadez, 2015). Furthermore, attempts to apply scientific knowledge should be useful for the professional field, and no hindering its functions. Therefore, it is not ideal to proscribe terms without taking into account their meaning within a specific conceptual proposal, and their respective disciplinary or professional scope (Perez-Almonacid, 2018). For example, no one would think of proscribing the term "atom", without considering Bohr's atomic model, just because the atom can be divided; or the term "vaccine" without considering the immunization model, just because cattle are no longer used in its manufacture. In this sense, a conceptual proposal, intended for a professional field, is primarily evaluated based on its objectives described in how much it helps to resolve the professional criterion, for example: better explanations for pathologies or for medical procedures measurable in terms of their evidence.

In conclusion, we presented a clearer and more logically valid view supporting the absence of dualism in Mental Health. This view is based on first defining Cartesian Dualism then showing that its component theses (Substance Dualism and Causal Interaction thesis) are incompatible between them (Burgos, 2016). Lastly, explain why assuming mental causation (i.e., mentalism) is incompatible with dualism, thus the first does not imply the second (Burgos & Killeen, 2019). In addition, we argue that (wrongly) accusing Mental Health as mentalist or dualist does not help the development of clinical research. In order not to incur a categorical error, clinical research should be criticized in its own terms such as efficacy of the treatments or how well a condition is understood. Psychological science does not prescribe social problems, nor accept or discard them. It is societies, through their professional institutions, who delimit their social problems through their values. If we ban the term Mental Health, we would not be contributing with the professionals that use this term in their daily life to help people. As a community, we must analyze whether scientistic strategies have yielded results in the field of Mental Health. But even more important is to move towards responsible clinical practices, respecting professional criteria based on evidence. For instance, following the evidence-based medicine movement (Sackett et al., 1996), which has already established a minimum criterion on which to build better contributions to the health field, and recently Interacciones has carried out a series of works in this area (Torres-Marruffo et al., 2024).

 

ORCID

Santiago Castiello De Obeso: https://orcid.org/0000-0002-3672-1366

Yancarlo Lizandro Ojeda Aguilar: https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9956-8365

Darwin Gutierrez-Guevara: https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9358-8402

 

AUTHORS’ CONTRIBUTION

Santiago Castiello De Obeso: Conceptualization, writing original draft, reviewing and editing.

Yancarlo Lizandro Ojeda Aguilar: Conceptualization, writing original draft, reviewing and editing.

Darwin Gutierrez-Guevara: Conceptualization, writing original draft, reviewing and editing.

 

FUNDING SOURCE

SCDO postdoctoral work is funded by the Templeton Foundation. YLOA postdoctoral work is funded by the Secretaria de Ciencia, Humanidades, Tecnología e Innovación (SECIHTI).

 

CONFLICT OF INTEREST

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

 

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

We are thankful with our professors from Centro de Estudios e Investigaciones en Comportamiento (CEIC), Universidad de Guadalajara, and Centro de Estudios e Investigaciones en Conocimiento y Aprendizaje Humano (CEICAH), Universidad Veracruzana. SCDO thanks Universidad de Guadalajara for his PhD institutional scholarship (V/2018/1476 and V/2021/989).

 

REVIEW PROCESS

This study has been reviewed by external peers in double-blind mode. The editor in charge was David Villarreal-Zegarra. The review process is included as supplementary material 1.

 

DATA AVAILABILITY STATEMENT

Not applicable

 

DECLARATION OF THE USE OF GENERATIVE ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE

The authors declare that they have not made use of artificial intelligence-generated tools for the creation of the manuscript, nor technological assistants for the writing of the manuscript.

 

DISCLAIMER

The authors are responsible for all statements made in this article.

 

REFERENCES

Baum, W. M. (2011). What is radical behaviorism? A review of Jay Moore’s conceptual foundations of radical behaviorism. Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior, 95, 119–126. https://doi.org/10.1901/jeab.2011.95-119

Burgos, J. E. (2016). Antidualism and antimentalism in radical behaviorism. Behavior and Philosophy, 43, 1–37.

Burgos, J. E. (2022). Un melodrama de la psicología. Revista de Psicología Universidad de Antioquia, 14(2), 1-30. https://doi.org/10.17533/udea.rp.e350101

Burgos, J. E., & Killeen, P. R. (2019). Suing for peace in the war against mentalism. Perspectives on Behavior Science, 42, 241-266. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40614-018-0169-2

Carpio, C., Pacheco Chávez, V., & Olvera Navas, V. (2024). Affective Behavioral Disturbances: An Interbehavioral Analysis. Interacciones, 10, 1-10. https://doi.org/10.24016/2024.v10.381

Descartes, R. (2013). The meditations on first philosophy, with selections from the objections and replies (J. Cottingham, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (original work published 1641)

Fonagy, P., Rost, F., Carlyle, J. A., McPherson, S., Thomas, R., Pasco Fearon, R. M., ... & Taylor, D. (2015). Pragmatic randomized controlled trial of long‐term psychoanalytic psychotherapy for treatment‐resistant depression: the Tavistock Adult Depression Study (TADS). World Psychiatry14(3), 312-321. https://doi.org/10.1002/wps.20267

Kantor, J. R. (1978). Cognition as events and as psychic constructions. The Psychological Record, 28, 329-342. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03394544

López Valadez, F. (2015). Teoría de la conducta, modos de conocimiento y modos de conocer. Universidad Veracruzana.

Miller, C. W., Ross, D. A., & Novick, A. M. (2020). “Not Dead Yet!”–confronting the legacy of dualism in modern psychiatry. Biological psychiatry, 87(7), e15-e17. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biopsych.2020.01.010

Pérez-Almonacid, R. (2018). Límites de la integración teórica en psicología. En: G. Gutierrez (Ed), Teorías en psicología: Integración y el futuro de la disciplina (pp. 24-67). Manual Moderno.

Rozemond, M. (1998). Descartes’ dualism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Rumelhart, D.E., Hinton, G.E. and Williams, R.J. (1986). Learning Internal Representations by Error Propagation. In: Rumelhart, D.E. and McClelland, J.L., The PDP Group, Eds., Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition, Volume 1, Foundations, MIT Press, Cambridge, 318-362.

Ryle, G. (2009). The concept of mind. Routledge.

Sackett, D. L., Rosenberg, W. M., Gray, J. M., Haynes, R. B., & Richardson, W. S. (1996). Evidence based medicine: what it is and what it isn't. BMJ, 312(7023), 71-72. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.312.7023.71

Shapiro, L. (Ed., Trans., 2007). Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes: The correspondence between Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Torres-Marruffo, D., Gutierrez-Guevara, D., & Salazar-Álvarez, G. (2024). Psychological practices based on evidence and health. Interacciones, e409-e409. https://doi.org/10.24016/2024.v10.409

Uttal, W. R. (2004). Dualism: the original sin of cognitivism. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Voss, S. (1993). Simplicity and the seat of the soul. In S. Voss (Ed.), Essays on the philosophy and science of René Descartes (pp. 128–141). Oxford: Oxford University Press.