http://dx.doi.org/10.24016/2025.v11.448
LETTER TO THE EDITOR
The term
“Mental” within Mental Health is not Dualist
Santiago
Castiello1, Yancarlo Lizandro Ojeda
Aguilar2, Darwin Gutierrez-Guevara3*
1 Wu Tsai Institute,
Yale University, United States
2 Universidad Autónoma
de Aguascalientes, Mexico
3 Asociación
Peruana Contextual Conductual de Psicología, Peru.
* Correspondencia: dgutierrezguevara@gmail.com.
Received: February 20, 2025 | Reviewed: March 05, 2024 | Accepted: March 09, 2025 | Published
Online: April 22, 2025.
CITARLO
COMO:
Castiello, S.,
Ojeda Aguilar, Y., Gutierrez-Guevara, D. (2025). The term “Mental” within Mental Health is
not Dualist. Interacciones, 11, e448.
http://dx.doi.org/10.24016/2025.v11.448
Dear Editor,
In a well written
piece published in Interacciones, Carpio et al. (2024) accused the concept of mental health as dualist.
Based on a theoretical analysis, our aims are
to address: (1) a philosophical issue with the accusations, and (2) comment on
the impact in the research community of these accusations. In this letter we
present a clearer and more valid view to a longstanding conflict in interbehaviourist psychology: Cartesian Dualism (CD)
usually referred to as dualism. Carpio and colleagues (C&all)
recapitulate a general critique to CD and used those arguments to flank the notion of Mental
Health. In addition, they proposed an interesting approach to analyze affective
disorders from an interbehaviourst framework,
nevertheless they provide an alternative concept for affective behavioral
change.
First,
we agree with C&all with respect that the World Health
Organization may not provide an exhaustive philosophical definition for the
concept of ‘mental’ when defining mental health. Although perhaps their goal is
not to provide exhaustive philosophical definitions but provide general
definitions for a common understanding of health. Second, we also agree that CD is
not the best fit for psychological science nor psychiatry (e.g., Miller
et al., 2020). Third, we agree that a common use of the mind as “internal” is
incompatible with CD (see more details in Burgos & Killeen, 2019).
However, we could not see references pointing to any Mental Health scientist
assuming CD and using the term “internal”.
Even if we agree
with some arguments from C&all, we disagree with
a core aspect in their work, a mistake also found elsewhere (e.g.,
Uttal, 2004; Kantor, 1978; Baum, 2011). The flaw in
their critique of Mental Health starts with the assumption that “mental”
implies CD. First, we define CD then we
explain C&all’s error theoretical mistake. CD is
comprised by two theses (Burgos, 2016): i)
the ontological thesis of Substance Dualism (SD) the res cogitans―soul
or mind― and res extensa―physical body― are substantially distinct (Rozemond, 1998); and the Causal
Interaction Thesis (CIT) mind and body are causally related. CD is the sum of
SD and CIT (Descartes, 1641/2013), i.e., the mind and the body are
fundamentally different substances (SD), and these substances hold a causal
relation (CIT). However, apart from CD and from a logical point of view, these
theses are independent, but also mutually exclusive. The dualistic aspect of CD
is given by SD and not by CIT. CD was rejected since its early development by
Pierre Gassendi (Voss, 1997) and Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia (Shapiro, 2007,
see details in Burgos, 2016). The bases of the rejection were: if mind and body
are different substances (SD), they cannot interact (~CIT). If they interact
(CIT), they cannot be part of the same substance (~SD), therefore one cannot
hold both SD and CIT. Generally, CIT is used to describe mentalism, which does
not assume SD.
In their
critique, C&all understand dualism as mind and
body being distinct and causally linked (i.e., CD), for
example: “causal relationship is again postulated between events, processes, or
mental events […] and the physical alterations” (pp. 3). However, postulating
mental causation implies that the mind and body cannot be different substances,
i.e., CIT à ~SD (CIT implies
the negation of SD). As shown before ―and as argued years ago by Pierre
Gassendi and Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia― it is logically invalid to hold
both SD and CIT as in the case of CD. Thus, C&all
accusations that mind-body causation imply dualism cannot be held. In the same
way, given that the concept of mental health implies mental causation (CIT, i.e.,
mentalism), automatically that mental health implies the absence of dualism.
Lastly, if psychiatrists would presume CD (i.e., accepting SD and CIT),
it would make no sense at all to prescribe medications, given that drugs only
directly affect the body, and would have no chance on changing the mind.
Mentalism, as the case of Mental Health via mental causation (CIT), is completely
compatible with a monist form such as materialism (Burgos, 2022). Mentalism turns also to be a good solution to
integrate neuroscience and psychology, and it turns out to be the philosophical
bases for psychologists who win Nobel Prizes, such as Geoffrey Hinton (e.g.,
Rumelhart, et al., 1986). But this is an issue beyond the scope of this letter.
A second and
distinct argument is at the sociological level. C&all
accuse researchers and professionals within the field
of Mental Health of being dualists, which as we describe above: is wrong. We believe declaring that mentalism and dualism are no scientific enough does not help for
the development of psychology in Latin America. Sustaining these types of
accusations demeaning Mental Health is to consider that all psychologies should
follow only one correct theory over all the others (e.g., interbehaviorism), irrespective of their context and
specific goals. Professional practice in Mental Health improves to the extent
that it can produce research that improve clinical outcomes in patients, e.g.,
psychoanalysis for long term depression (Fonagy, et al., 2015).
Accusing the WHO
for not having an adequate philosophical definition of Mental Health,
regardless of the circumstantial use of the term, is a categorical error (Ryle,
2009; López Valadez, 2015). Furthermore, attempts to apply scientific knowledge
should be useful for the professional field, and no hindering its functions.
Therefore, it is not ideal to proscribe terms without taking
into account their meaning within a specific conceptual proposal, and
their respective disciplinary or professional scope (Perez-Almonacid, 2018).
For example, no one would think of proscribing the term "atom",
without considering Bohr's atomic model, just because the atom can be divided;
or the term "vaccine" without considering the immunization model,
just because cattle are no longer used in its manufacture. In this sense, a
conceptual proposal, intended for a professional field, is primarily evaluated
based on its objectives described in how much it helps to resolve the
professional criterion, for example: better explanations for pathologies or for
medical procedures measurable in terms of their evidence.
In conclusion, we
presented a clearer and more logically valid view supporting the absence of
dualism in Mental Health. This view is based on first defining Cartesian
Dualism then showing that its component theses (Substance Dualism and Causal
Interaction thesis) are incompatible between them (Burgos, 2016). Lastly,
explain why assuming mental causation (i.e., mentalism) is incompatible
with dualism, thus the first does not imply the second (Burgos & Killeen,
2019). In addition, we argue that (wrongly) accusing Mental Health as mentalist
or dualist does not help the development of clinical research. In order not to
incur a categorical error, clinical research should be criticized in its own
terms such as efficacy of the treatments or how well a
condition is understood. Psychological science does not prescribe social
problems, nor accept or discard them. It is societies, through their
professional institutions, who delimit their social problems through their values.
If we ban the term Mental Health, we would not be contributing with the
professionals that use this term in their daily life to help people. As a
community, we must analyze whether scientistic strategies have yielded results
in the field of Mental Health. But even more important is to move towards
responsible clinical practices, respecting professional criteria based on
evidence. For instance, following the evidence-based medicine movement (Sackett
et al., 1996), which has already established a minimum criterion on which to
build better contributions to the health field, and recently Interacciones
has carried out a series of works in this area (Torres-Marruffo et al., 2024).
ORCID
Santiago Castiello De Obeso: https://orcid.org/0000-0002-3672-1366
Yancarlo
Lizandro Ojeda Aguilar: https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9956-8365
Darwin Gutierrez-Guevara: https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9358-8402
AUTHORS’ CONTRIBUTION
Santiago Castiello De Obeso: Conceptualization,
writing original draft, reviewing and editing.
Yancarlo Lizandro Ojeda Aguilar: Conceptualization,
writing original draft, reviewing and editing.
Darwin Gutierrez-Guevara: Conceptualization,
writing original draft, reviewing and editing.
FUNDING SOURCE
SCDO postdoctoral work is funded by the Templeton
Foundation. YLOA postdoctoral work is funded by the Secretaria
de Ciencia, Humanidades, Tecnología
e Innovación (SECIHTI).
CONFLICT OF INTEREST
The authors declare no conflict of
interest.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
We are thankful with our professors from Centro de Estudios e Investigaciones en Comportamiento
(CEIC), Universidad de Guadalajara, and Centro de Estudios e Investigaciones en
Conocimiento y Aprendizaje Humano (CEICAH), Universidad Veracruzana. SCDO thanks Universidad de Guadalajara for his PhD institutional
scholarship (V/2018/1476 and V/2021/989).
REVIEW PROCESS
This study has been reviewed by external peers in double-blind mode.
The editor in charge was David Villarreal-Zegarra. The review process is
included as supplementary material 1.
DATA AVAILABILITY STATEMENT
Not applicable
DECLARATION OF THE USE OF GENERATIVE ARTIFICIAL
INTELLIGENCE
The authors declare that they have not made use of artificial
intelligence-generated tools for the creation of the manuscript, nor
technological assistants for the writing of the manuscript.
DISCLAIMER
The authors are responsible for all statements made in this article.
REFERENCES
Baum, W. M.
(2011). What is radical behaviorism? A review of Jay
Moore’s conceptual foundations of radical behaviorism.
Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior,
95, 119–126. https://doi.org/10.1901/jeab.2011.95-119
Burgos, J. E.
(2016). Antidualism and antimentalism
in radical behaviorism. Behavior and Philosophy, 43, 1–37.
Burgos, J. E. (2022). Un melodrama de la
psicología. Revista de Psicología Universidad de Antioquia, 14(2), 1-30.
https://doi.org/10.17533/udea.rp.e350101
Burgos, J. E.,
& Killeen, P. R. (2019). Suing for peace in the war against mentalism. Perspectives
on Behavior Science, 42, 241-266. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40614-018-0169-2
Carpio, C.,
Pacheco Chávez, V., & Olvera Navas, V. (2024). Affective Behavioral Disturbances: An Interbehavioral
Analysis. Interacciones, 10, 1-10. https://doi.org/10.24016/2024.v10.381
Descartes, R.
(2013). The meditations on first philosophy, with selections from the
objections and replies (J. Cottingham, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press (original work published 1641)
Fonagy, P., Rost,
F., Carlyle, J. A., McPherson, S., Thomas, R., Pasco Fearon, R. M., ... &
Taylor, D. (2015). Pragmatic randomized controlled trial of long‐term
psychoanalytic psychotherapy for treatment‐resistant depression: the Tavistock
Adult Depression Study (TADS). World Psychiatry, 14(3),
312-321. https://doi.org/10.1002/wps.20267
Kantor, J. R.
(1978). Cognition as events and as psychic constructions. The Psychological
Record, 28, 329-342. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03394544
López Valadez, F.
(2015). Teoría de
la conducta, modos de conocimiento y modos de conocer. Universidad Veracruzana.
Miller, C. W., Ross, D. A., & Novick, A. M. (2020). “Not Dead
Yet!”–confronting the legacy of dualism in modern psychiatry. Biological psychiatry, 87(7), e15-e17. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biopsych.2020.01.010
Pérez-Almonacid, R. (2018). Límites de la
integración teórica en psicología. En: G. Gutierrez
(Ed), Teorías en psicología: Integración y el futuro de la disciplina
(pp. 24-67). Manual Moderno.
Rozemond, M.
(1998). Descartes’ dualism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rumelhart, D.E.,
Hinton, G.E. and Williams, R.J. (1986). Learning Internal Representations by
Error Propagation. In: Rumelhart, D.E. and McClelland, J.L., The PDP Group,
Eds., Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of
Cognition, Volume 1, Foundations, MIT Press, Cambridge, 318-362.
Ryle, G. (2009). The
concept of mind. Routledge.
Sackett, D. L.,
Rosenberg, W. M., Gray, J. M., Haynes, R. B., & Richardson, W. S. (1996).
Evidence based medicine: what it is and what it isn't. BMJ, 312(7023),
71-72. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.312.7023.71
Shapiro, L. (Ed.,
Trans., 2007). Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes: The
correspondence between Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Torres-Marruffo,
D., Gutierrez-Guevara, D., & Salazar-Álvarez, G. (2024). Psychological
practices based on evidence and health. Interacciones, e409-e409.
https://doi.org/10.24016/2024.v10.409
Uttal, W. R. (2004). Dualism: the
original sin of cognitivism. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Voss, S. (1993).
Simplicity and the seat of the soul. In S. Voss (Ed.), Essays on the
philosophy and science of René Descartes (pp. 128–141). Oxford: Oxford University
Press.